Abstract
The close study of literary texts has a long and illustrious history. But the
popularity of textual analysis has waned in recent decades, just at the time that
widely available electronic texts were making traditional analytic tools easier to
apply and encouraging the development of innovative computer-assisted tools. Without
claiming any simple causal relationship, I argue that the marginalization of textual
analysis and other text-centered approaches owes something to the dominance of
Chomskyan linguistics and the popularity of high theory. Certainly both an
introspective, sentence-oriented, formalist linguistic approach and literary theories
deeply influenced by ideas about the sign's instability and the tendency of texts to
disintegrate under critical pressure minimize the importance of the text. Using
examples from Noam Chomsky, Jerome McGann, and Stanley Fish, I argue for a return to
the text, specifically the electronic, computable text, to see what corpora,
text-analysis, statistical stylistics, and authorship attribution can reveal about
meanings and style. The recent resurgence of interest in scholarly editions, corpora,
text- analysis, stylistics, and authorship suggest that the electronic text may
finally reach its full potential.
Introduction
Unfortunately for the history of digital humanities, the advent of widely available
electronic texts coincided with the Chomsky years in linguistics and the theory years
in literary studies. Although these orthodoxies rest on very different theoretical
underpinnings, they both tend to deny the legitimacy of text-analysis and stylistics.
They de-emphasize the close study of texts and cast doubt on its significance and
centrality.
Chomsky’s mentalist approach, which has dominated American linguistics for more than
forty years, locates its site of interest in the mind and treats texts and other
stretches of naturally occurring language almost as irrelevant excrescences on the
body of the innate language organ. It emphasizes the formal nature of grammar,
downplays semantics, focuses on competence/deep structure rather than textual domain
of performance/surface structure, ignores literature, and restricts itself to the
scope of the sentence.
Much high theory is deeply influenced by ideas about the instability of the sign and
the tendency of texts to disintegrate under critical pressure, ideas most closely
associated with the late Jacques Derrida. Theory has had almost nothing to say about
Chomsky, focusing instead on Saussure, a linguist whose ideas are more congenial, at
least in the sense that they discuss the process of signification at length. Jerome
McGann, for example, champions the game-like, “fundamentally subjective character of . . . criticism”
[
McGann 2004, 50–1] and asks “What if the question isn’t ‘
how could he [the critic] take himself or his ideas seriously’
but ‘why
should he take himself or his ideas seriously’?”
[
McGann 2004, 50]. Stanley Fish emphasizes the reader’s role,
attacking the idea that texts have meaning at all–arguing that the only links that
exist between the text and its interpretation are those that are “fashioned in response to the demands of the reading
experience”
[
Fish 1980, 64]. Critical approaches like these and a more general
distrust of the sign/signified link within literary theory helped to produce a
climate inhospitable to text-analysis and stylistics.
It is not necessary to insist on any direct causal relationship between the hegemony
of Chomskyan linguistics and high theory and the marginalization of textual analysis
and other text-centered approaches, but, whatever their other merits, these two
influential trends have certainly helped to keep the tremendous potential of
electronic texts for literary study from being realized. Recently, however, there
have been signs of a resurgence of interest in scholarly editions, corpora,
text-analysis, stylistics, and authorship that suggest that the electronic text may
finally reach its full potential. Because the point I want to make is such a basic
one, I will present only a couple of very simple ways of returning to the text,
merely mentioning some more sophisticated methods in my conclusion. The nature of the
methodology is less important than the reestablishment of the text as the central
focus of inquiry, as one of the most important objects of study.
Chomsky, Innateness, and the Irrelevant Text
Let us begin with Chomsky, and one of the most characteristic and important
principles of his theory: the innateness of linguistic ability. If it is not
immediately apparent that a belief that human language is largely the result of a set
of innate mechanisms necessarily devalues texts, an examination of one of the most
central of Chomsky’s arguments for innateness quickly shows why this is so. In a move
that harkens back to Plato’s argument for innate ideas, Chomsky argues that language
learning would be impossible without a rich, specifically linguistic innate mental
structure. The facts that a native speaker knows about the language, he argues, are
too complex, too subtle, too regular, and too unpredictable to have been learned from
the language to which the child has been exposed. Because the speaker manifestly
knows them, there must be an innate language component that allows the speaker to
“acquire” language (not “learn” it) with extreme rapidity, without
explicit instruction, and on the basis of evidence that is inadequate and often
corrupt.
This is not the place to examine all of Chomsky’s arguments (for a thorough and
careful critique of the innateness hypothesis and various arguments for it, see [
Sampson 2005]). For my purposes, however, I will focus on the last
argument, that the evidence to which the child is exposed is inadequate and corrupt.
Although it is increasingly clear that the language children are exposed to is less
corrupt than Chomsky supposed (why he supposed it rather than examining it is another
aspect of the devaluation of text), but the more important question for the history
and future of the study of texts is whether his argument from lack of evidence is
persuasive, whether it is true that speakers know things for which they have no
relevant experience. Another way of framing his argument is to say that the
“texts” on the basis of which a child comes to know a language are faulty,
incomplete, and insufficient. Given that, why study them?
One classic and often-repeated kind of evidence for innateness comes from question
formation in English. How can a child determine the correct form of the question
version of “The man is tall”
[
Chomsky 1975, 31]? The simplest rule that the child might
entertain is that the first verb moves to the front, which correctly gives “Is the
man tall?” But in “The man who is tall is in the room,” this simple rule
gives the wrong question form: “*Is the man who tall is in the room?” (Here, as
is usual in linguistic discussions, the asterisk marks an ungrammatical form.) The
correct rule requires that the child analyze the grammatical structure of the
sentence and apply a more accurate but more complicated rule: move the first verb
after the first noun phrase of the main sentence to the front [
Chomsky 1975, 31–2]. The crucial argument for innateness is that,
as Chomsky puts it, “A person may go
through a considerable part of his life without ever facing relevant evidence, but
he will have no hesitation in using the structure-dependent rule, even if all of
his experience is consistent with” the simpler rule [
Chomsky 1975, 32]. Because all speakers of English arrive at a rule
for which they often have no relevant evidence, knowledge of grammatical principles
must be innate.
In his wonderful book,
The “Language Instinct”
Debate, Geoffrey Sampson uses textual evidence from corpora very
effectively to counter this classic argument for innateness. He presents “The subjects who have acted as controls will
be paid” as his example of a sentence for which the simple rule gives the
incorrect result. He notes that Blake’s “Did he who made the lamb make thee?” is an example of counter-evidence
that most school children will be exposed to, and then finds that 12% of all yes/no
questions in a 40 million word
Wall Street Journal
corpus from 1987-89 are of a form that would contradict the potentially wrong rule
[
Sampson 2005, 46–47]. There is thus no reason to think that
speakers lack the relevant evidence against the simple form of the question rule, and
one of Chomsky’s central arguments for innateness loses much of its force. What
Sampson’s example makes clear is that Chomsky’s reliance on intuition and his
rejection of textual evidence leads him to base a central premise of his innateness
hypothesis on the non-existence of sentence types that actually occur fairly
frequently.
In fairness, when Chomsky first presented this argument, there were no huge corpora
for him to examine, and some of the subtle grammatical facts upon which his arguments
depend are so infrequent that it would have been quixotic to have searched for
examples. Yet the grounds for Chomsky’s rejection of corpora and of the evidence of
texts are more theoretical than practical, so that the subsequent availability of
huge corpora has had almost no impact on the Chomskyan tradition.
A second claim for an innate grammatical principle that can be contested using
electronic corpora involves the following sentences:
(1)
- a. John was (too) clever to catch.
- b. John was (too) clever to be caught.
- c. John was (too) easy to catch.
- d. John was (too) easy to be caught.
[Chomsky 2000, 168]
Chomsky argues that an innate Faculty of Language (FL) that is “common to the species, assuming states that vary in limited
ways with experience”
[
Chomsky 2000, 168] is required to explain how a person can
produce sentences like (1a-d), and understand some surprising features of their
meaning. Chomsky’s important insights about such sentences involve agency and the
question of what the adjective modifies. As he suggests, with “too,” they don’t
catch John in (1a-b) and “clever” modifies John. It is unclear whether or not
they catch John in (1c-d) (“John was easy for them to catch, so they didn’t
bother.”), but the catching is “easy,” not John. We may all agree that
these are interesting observations, especially because the sentences seem so similar
in structure, but not everyone agrees that (1d) is deviant, as his proposed innate
principle requires. Phrases like “easy to be caught” are so rare that
Wall Street Journal corpus and even the 100 million word
British National Corpus (BNC) are too small to provide sufficient examples for
analysis, though I did find the following tantalizing parallel to the deviant form in
1d in Mark Davies new 100+ million word
Time Magazine corpus
(2007): “The Clinton are just not easy to be
caught by a pumpkin head”
[
Trillin 1998]. Chomsky’s argument is not tied to any particular verb, however, so that we
can also consider the exactly parallel sentence with a more common verb: “John was
easy to find/easy to be found.” Chomsky’s argument obviously entails the
deviance of the passive version of this sentence, but counterexamples to his views
are too easy to be found in real sentences for them to be taken seriously. My
preceding sentence violates his claim, as do thousands of sentences that a Google
search for “easy to be found” (7/16/06) returns.
Although Google is neither a good nor a representative corpus, my interest here is
in naturally occurring texts. Thus it seems reasonable to allow Google’s enormous
body of texts to act as a corpus, so long as its limitations are acknowledged.
Chomsky’s argument, remember, is that “John
is easy to be caught” violates an innate principle of grammar, so that the
presence of large numbers of examples of this construction, even in a relatively poor
corpus, should count as evidence against his theory.
Chomsky might reject many of the Google hits as modern, casual examples, ones in
which “performance” might not match “competence.” The search also uncovers
many examples from standard edited English, however. The fact that these were
discovered using Google is clearly unimportant, and the relatively long list below
makes its own point (each was accessed at the listed URL on July 16, 2006):
For nothing is more easy to be found, then
be barking Scyllas, ravening Celenos, and Loestrygonians devourers of people,
and such like great, and incredible monsters.
[More 1914]
And the reason why the MACEDONIANS kept so
easily dominion over them was owing to other causes easy to be found in the
historians . . . .
[Hume 1748]
But, he himself was less easy to be
found; for, he had led a wandering life, and settled people had lost sight of
him.
[Dickens 1858]
Also many precedents of ill success and
lamentable miseries befallen others in the like designs were easy to be found,
and not forgotten to be alleged.
[Bradford 1647]
It has been said, that he used
unprecedented and improper instruments of correction. Of this accusation the
meaning is not very easy to be found.
[Boswell 1791]
eaþ-fynde; adj. Easy to be found;
facilis inventu:-- Ðá wæs eáþfynde.
[Bosworth and Toller 1898]
Then a trail on land is not easy to be
found in the dark.
[Cooper 1840]
May they bring hither hundreds,
thousands for our men: may they bring hidden stores to light, and make wealth
easy to be found.
[Griffith 1896]
One of them, she who drank out of the
red-head's cup, so fair, and with such a pleasant slim grace, that her like
were not easy to be found.
[Morris 1895]
Mark then the goal, 'tis easy to be found;
/ Yon aged trunk, a cubit from the ground.
[Pope 1715-20]
Besides, there grows a flower in marshy
ground, / Its name amellus, easy to be found.
[Addison 1694]
Avoid the rocks on Britain's angry shore.
/ They lie, alas! too easy to be found; / For thee alone they lie the island
round.
[Swift 1726]
“Hang on a minute,” I hear the reader say. “You seem to be telling us
that this man who is by common consent the world’s leading living
intellectual, according to Cambridge University a second Plato, is basing
his radical reassessment of human nature largely on the claim that a certain
thing never happens; he tells us that it strains his credulity to think that
it might happen, but he has never looked, and people who have looked find
that it happens a lot.”
Yes, that’s about the size of it. Funny old world, isn’t it! [Sampson 2005, 47]
One of Chomsky’s standard arguments that might seem to save his innate principle
from such textual evidence is that there is no necessary connection between our
knowledge of language (competence), and our ability to use it (performance) [
Chomsky 1986, 8–13] for an extended discussion). And this argument
shows how central the devaluation of text is to the theory. Yet it seems unreasonable
to argue that Swift had the innate “knowledge” that “easy to be found”
violates a grammatical principle but lacked the “ability” to apply this
knowledge in a formal, edited, poetic context, or that his editors, with the same
innate knowledge, somehow failed to notice that the sentence is ungrammatical. Errors
do find their way into print, but the existence of tens of thousands of examples
(including those with other verbs than “found”) from the seventeenth century to
the present both undermines Chomsky’s evidence for this innate principle of grammar
and supports the usefulness and validity of corpus-based text-analytic methods of
language study.
Needless to say, Chomsky’s theory does not rest entirely on this principle, and it
could be revised so as to eliminate this “knowledge” from the claimed competence
of the English speaker. Yet exceptions to principles of grammar that Chomsky claims
are universal and innate and uses as central pieces of evidence for the innateness
hypothesis are so frequent and so easily found (or easy to be found) as to suggest
that his theory will eventually have to come to terms with them if it is to survive.
Natural language corpora are becoming so large that they can now realistically be
used to test the linguist’s intuitions about what sentences are ungrammatical. And it
will not do to suggest that those who use the “deviant” passives have a
different grammar, if the deviance is derived from a principle that is claimed to be
innate. Corpora can also be used to search for grammatical structures that have not
yet been integrated into linguistic theory, and so can enrich our understanding of
human language. They can also be used to investigate the relationship between
competence and performance, or, perhaps more radically, to evaluate Chomsky’s claims
about this distinction.
Literary Theory and the Irrelevant Text
Let us turn now from the world of linguistics to the world of high theory, while
also keeping in mind the important and foundational position of Derrida’s critique of
Sassure as a connection between linguistics and theory. Despite the connection,
however, the devaluation of the text that is associated with literary theory is of a
very different kind. Rather than turning our attention from texts to the mind as an
object of study, high theory remains in the world of texts, but casts doubt on the
usefulness of approaches to the style and meaning of texts that are central to
textual analysis.
I have no quarrel with the playful and ingenious deconstruction of binaries that is
often found in deconstructive criticism. Nor do I deny the power or value of the
general poststructuralist critique that dismantles the naive view of the text as a
transparent conduit for the transmission of messages. I would like to argue instead
that skeptical doubts about the connection between words and the world are too often
taken to the extreme, that the seductive lure of skeptical relativism and very
reasonable distrust of reductive and global claims often push poststructuralist
arguments past the breaking point.
I will sketch out a few of the ways in which returning our attention to the text can
enhance our understanding and appreciation of literary texts. I will make no attempt
to be comprehensive, but will instead argue that text-centered approaches, especially
now that they can be augmented with computational tools, offer a more revealing and
more productive approach–one that can give access to kinds of information that is not
available through other means, and can at least begin to reveal how texts are
structured and how they work.
Jerome McGann, Deformance, and the Almost Irrelevant Text
Jerome McGann’s
Radiant Textuality: Literature after the
World Wide Web
[
McGann 2004] is an influential, provocative, and valuable book that
forces the reader to confront profound and important questions about the stability
of texts and the nature of interpretation. McGann uses an experiment involving the
scanning and optical character recognition of a Victorian periodical to show that
texts are unstable under one kind of machine-assisted “reading.” He argues
that instability is an inherent feature of all texts, that texts “are not containers of meaning or data but
sets of rules (algorithms) for generating themselves: for discovering,
organizing, and utilizing meanings and data”
[
McGann 2004, 138]. This is a valuable insight–one that helps
the reader to see more clearly the kinds of problems that textual editors have
long had to deal with (see Peter Shillingsburg’s
From
Gutenberg to Google, 2007 for an illuminating recent discussion). I
have argued elsewhere that McGann overestimates the instability of the text [
Hoover 2006]. Here I want to focus on the way it devalues textual
evidence and turns the critic’s attention away from the text.
One consequence of the definition of texts as algorithms for generating
themselves is that each generation is potentially unique, a product of the
algorithms and the interpreting mind. For McGann, this suggests a recuperation of
an old but recently neglected kind of performative criticism that he suggests can
open the text to interesting new readings. The performative critic practices what
McGann calls “deformance” by manipulating the order of the textual elements
and even changing them. For example, after printing the lines of Wallace Steven’s
“The Snow Man” in reverse order, McGann argues that
deformance accentuates the intelligibility of the text and “clarifies the secondary status of the
interpretation”
[
McGann 2004, 120]. He then prints only the nouns of the poem,
leaving them in roughly their original positions and arguing that doing so shows
it to be a noun-heavy and noun-balanced poem. (The word “poem” here is
intended as uncontroversial shorthand for “poetic text.” Poems are typically
more highly structured than prose texts, and provide additional opportunities for
deformance, so that it is often important to distinguish them.)
Having practiced deformance (under the name of text alteration) for twenty-five
years, I can hardly object to it in principle. It does seem to me, however, that
the practice of textual deformance is most valuable when it is turned back upon
the original text as a tool of interpretation (see
Hoover (2004a),
Hoover (2006)). Printing
only the nouns is an effective way of focusing attention on them, and any
deformance initially requires close attention to the text. When its aims are a
better understanding of the text, it allows the critic to uncover previously
hidden relationships among the parts of the text and to examine the nature of its
self-generating algorithm. But when the focus is on performing with the poem, on
uncovering “uncommon critical
possibilities”
[
McGann 2004, 51], the critic’s attention is turned away from
the text. This turn is crucial, I would argue, precisely because the text
otherwise exercises a powerful coercive effect on interpretation and limits the
critical possibilities. Textual algorithms normally constrain or direct the
reader’s activities. Although the algorithms for generating
Jane Eyre and
Wuthering Heights were
written by sisters and published the same year, they are radically different and
lead to radically different readings. Even the amount and nature of a text’s
instability are at least partly a function of its algorithms.
There is no space here for an extended argument for textual analysis, but McGann’s
deformation of “The Snow Man” suggests an alternative,
text-centered kind of marking that points in a useful direction. Below are “The Snow Man” and excerpts of about the same length from
two other poems with the nouns highlighted:
As these marked excerpts suggest, “The Snow Man” turns
out to be a noun-average poem rather than a noun-heavy one, as I have shown by
examining the frequency of nouns in twenty-five roughly contemporary poets [
Hoover 2006].
A fuller analysis of the number, character, and arrangement of nouns in poems is
worthwhile and would almost certainly lead to further insights about the poems
(see [
Hoover 2006] for more discussion; also [
Hoover 2007]). Even a brief inspection of these excerpts, however,
shows that the nouns in Sandburg’s poem are not only much more frequent than those
in “The Snow Man,” they are much more concrete and
specific. They ground and localize the fictional world of the poem much more fully
than do the nouns of “The Snow Man,” and their rural
and regional flavor is unmistakable. In Millay’s poem, the nouns are much less
frequent than those in “The Snow Man,” and they seem
relatively prosaic. The power of the poem lies elsewhere.
Printing only the nouns of a poem in their original positions in the poem can
lead to a wider investigation into the kinds, frequencies, and placements of nouns
in other poems, via textual or corpus analysis. Such an investigation can tell us
a great deal about Stevens’s poem and about modern poetry more generally. Instead,
however, McGann turns away from the poem toward his own algorithm, arguing that
printing only the nouns “enhances the
significance of the page’s white space, which now appears as a poetic
equivalent for the physical ‘nothing’ of snow”
[
McGann 2004, 123]. Rather than focusing on the poem, he bases
his reading on the white space of a poem Stevens did not write, white space that
is present in any poem deformed in this way, whether or not whiteness or snow is
in any way relevant to its interpretation. This kind of argument abandons all hope
of persuasion or consensus and turns criticism into a purely subjective and
self-indulgent activity.
Consider the following deformation of Edgar Allan Poe’s “The
Raven”:
Note how this deformation enhances the significance of the black type, allowing it
to appear as a poetic equivalent of the physical “nothing” of the blackness
of the Raven. If you look closely, you can see the raven’s beady eyes peeking over
the top of the first line. If you look again, you can see how Poe anticipated the
Borg ship from Star Trek: The Next Generation. Being
provocative is just not enough, and the black and white nature of most printed
text assures that symbolism based on black ink or white paper is unlikely to be
more than coincidentally relevant. The currency of ideas still stranger than those
in McGann’s book in published literary criticism rather proves than disproves my
point.
Stanley Fish and the Missing Inuit
Stanley Fish is another provocative thinker whose provocations radically devalue
the text and push the reader away from an important source of insight. Although
Fish’s thought has had many phases, I am concerned here with his early and very
influential book,
Is There a Text in this Class?
[
Fish 1980]. There, Fish reports and critiques a comment by Norman
Holland about unacceptable readings — a comment based on an unusual interpretation
of the following passage from Faulkner’s “A Rose for
Emily”:
That was when people had begun to feel
really sorry for her. People in our town, remembering how old lady Wyatt, her
great-aunt, had gone completely crazy at last, believed that the Griersons held
themselves a little too high for what they really were. None of the young men
were quite good enough for Miss Emily and such. We had long thought of them as
a tableau; Miss Emily a slender figure in white in the background, her father a
spraddled silhouette in the foreground, his back to her and clutching a
horsewhip, the two of them framed by the back-flung front door. So when she got
to be thirty and was still single, we were not pleased exactly, but vindicated;
even with insanity in the family she wouldn't have turned down all of her
chances if they had really materialized.
[Faulkner 1978, 434]
Holland suggests that if a reader believed that the “tableau” above
“described an Eskimo,” he or she would not be thought of as “responding to the story at all–only pursuing
some mysterious inner exploration”
[
Fish 1980, 346]. Fish agrees that the Eskimo reading is
unacceptable, but argues that it is unacceptable not because the text does not
support it, but because no current interpretive strategy exists for producing such
a reading:
While there are always mechanisms for
ruling out readings, their source is not the text but the presently
recognized interpretive strategies for producing the text. It follows, then,
that no reading, however outlandish it might appear, is inherently an
impossible one.
[Fish 1980, 347]
He imagines someone finding a letter in which Faulkner says he always believed he
was an Eskimo changeling and suggests that Faulkner critics would then “transform the text into one informed
everywhere by Eskimo meanings.”
[
Fish 1980, 346]
Fish’s argument is as specious as it is clever. Holland’s example of an Eskimo
reading is clearly chosen so as to avoid any resonance with the text: most readers
will know only a little stereotypical information about Eskimo culture, and an
igloo would not last very long in Yoknapatawpha County. (Eskimo is
now normally replaced by Inuit. The changing political status of
words like Eskimo is an area in which Fish’s point about the changing
meaning of texts is valuable, though not very provocative or controversial.) It
might be possible to integrate the (widely misunderstood) practice of wife sharing
into the tableau in some bizarre way, but if Fish’s point is only that we are
quite adept at finding what we want to find, that is hardly a novel or provocative
idea, and is certainly not a critical method that should be encouraged.
A letter from Faulkner revealing that he always thought of himself as an Inuit
changeling is unlikely to be sufficient to support an Inuit reading. How would
being a changeling imbue his texts with Inuit meanings in any case? What is
signally missing from “A Rose for Emily” is any actual
textual reference to Inuit culture, and Holland’s point is far more specific than
the version Fish rejects: being “informed” by Inuit readings is not much like
“describing an Eskimo,” so that Fish’s imagined letter is simply
irrelevant to Holland’s point. (Note that the claim that the meaning is not in the
text effectively insulates Fish against this kind of criticism.) If critics really
reacted as Fish suggests they would, so much the worse for criticism, but it seems
far more likely that, because of the nature of Faulkner’s texts,
either such a letter would be rejected as a forgery or critics would wonder why
being a changeling had so little influence on his writing. Readings can and do
change over time, sometimes radically, and critics like Fish are partly
responsible for the current tolerance for a greater distance between the text and
its interpretation than might have existed in the past. Still, interpretations are
not as independent of the text as Fish suggests, and he ignores the huge overlap
between even the most violently contrasting interpretations, the sources of which,
given the variety among the interpretive communities that he suggests are
responsible for the interpretations, surely include the text. For that matter, it
is difficult to imagine the formation of the kind of interpretive community Fish
posits in the absence of a body of shared texts.
Professor Fish, is there a textbook for this course?
One of Fish’s most famous examples, “Is
there a text in this class?”, the title of his book, is also deeply
problematic. A student who has just taken a class from Fish asks this question on
the first day of class of another professor who takes it to be a question about
whether there is a required textbook. The student corrects the professor: “No, no . . . I mean in this class do we
believe in poems and things, or is it just us?”
[
Fish 1980, 305]. Fish’s insistence on the importance of
context for interpretation is valuable, and it provides a welcome change from the
single-sentence focus of Chomskyan linguistics. Of central importance here is his
claim that we interpret such a sentence by virtue of belonging to an interpretive
community in which it makes sense and not by virtue of the meanings of its words
or their syntactic relationships. In what follows I will focus on this claim, but
also on the question itself and what he has to say about it.
Fish discusses the two meanings of the question above and suggests a third
possibility — that the student is asking about the location of her misplaced book
(my paraphrases follow each one):
- Is there a text in this class?1 Is there
a required textbook for this course?
- Is there a text in this class?2 Will this
course assume the meaningfulness of texts?
- Is there a text in this class?3 Is my
misplaced textbook in this classroom?
[Fish 1980, 306–7]
He argues that all of these are literal, and that they all arise out of the
context, not out of the text. It is a tribute to Fish’s skill at argumentation
that the extreme form of his position has been taken seriously. It is apparent,
for example, that the words of the sentence and their syntactic arrangement deeply
influence all three of these meanings (how did the professor know it was a
question?), and that the crux of the matter is the ambiguity of “text,”
“in,” and “class” that my paraphrases highlight. Given the importance he
places on interpretive communities, it is surprising that Fish refuses to
acknowledge one of the largest and most important of the interpretive communities
relevant to this example: speakers of English. In that community, there are such
things as meanings of words (of course not Platonic forms or Aristotelian
categories), meanings that are, as he rightly points out, more or less profoundly
affected by the context of use, broadly understood to include things like the
other interpretive communities to which the professor and student belong.
Given Fish’s valuable emphasis on the contextual nature of meaning, it also seems
surprising that the text should be denied a part in the creation of that meaning.
Fish is surely right that the relationships, contexts, and interpretive
communities that surround or constitute his classroom tableau, as well as the
personal histories of the student and professor are crucial to the professor’s
understanding of the student’s question, and to her ability to produce it. But the
question itself is also an important element in the entire exchange. “What are
your office hours?” spoken in the identical context (first day of class, the
same student and professor, etc.) obviously means something very different and
calls for a radically different set of possible answers. However problematically,
the sources of difference must include the language of the question. The practice
of holding office hours, their nature, their typical format and scheduling and
their institutional status–all of their meaning in the academic interpretive
community–is partially dependent on the words “office” and “hours” and
how those words are used, both in English generally, and within that community. To
put it another way, one of the chief ways one becomes a member of an interpretive
community is by learning to understand and respond to its texts appropriately.
But let us return to the text. Fish suggests that, while none of the meanings is
the only literal one, “Is there a required textbook for this course?” is
“more normal” than “Will this course assume the meaningfulness of
texts?” (he does not further discuss the third meaning). He argues that the
first meaning has a broader context of understanding (the participants need only
know roughly what is normal in the context of the first day of class), and the
second a narrower, more specialized one (the participants need to know something
about Fish’s literary theory). The fact that the student and the professor could
only have come to the required knowledge through reading and listening to Fish’s
ideas, however, makes his cavalier neglect of the words of the text seem little
more than a debater’s trick.
But if we use corpora to investigate the crucial phrase “text in this class”
and some variants of it, we gain access to evidence about how that huge
interpretive community called “speakers of English” actually uses the phrase.
Unfortunately, the phrase is not common enough for the BNC to be of much use,
though the fact that the only instance of “text in this class” in the BNC is
a reference to the title of Fish’s book is significant, as will become clear
shortly. Turning again to Google (search for “text in this class”, 7/20/06),
we find that nearly 90% of about 31,200 uses of the phrase are direct references
to Fish’s book, and only about 6% mean “Is there a required textbook for this
course?” (My counts are based on a manual examination of 500 hits taken from
throughout the 1,000 that Google provides; the results should be taken as
suggestive rather than in any way definitive.) This proportion is a tribute to the
importance of the book since 1980. A search for “text for this class” returns
about 18,300 hits, almost all of which mean “Is there a required textbook for
this course?” Here are the frequencies of some related phrases, with those
already discussed repeated for clarity:
text for this class |
18,300 |
text in this class |
31,200 |
texts for this class |
890 |
texts in this class |
200 |
text for this course |
81,600 |
text in this course |
750 |
texts for this course |
31,100 |
textbook for this class |
19,600 |
textbook in this class |
110 |
textbooks for this class |
450 |
textbooks in this class |
20 |
textbook for this course |
102,000 |
textbook in this course |
80 |
textbooks for this course |
93,200 |
syllabus for this class |
10,300 |
syllabus in this class |
50 |
syllabus for this course |
52,700 |
syllabus in this course |
100 |
Currently, it would seem, “text in this class” is quite an unusual way of
indicating “textbook for this course,” the meaning that Fish suggests is the
most normal. The preposition “for” is normal while “in” is unusual:
overall, not counting “text for/in this class,” phrases with “for” are
almost 200 times as frequent as those with “in.” Furthermore, “course”
and “textbook” are more frequent than “class” and “text.” The
professor’s initial interpretation is (obviously) a possible one, and it may be
more normal now than in 1980 because of the influence of the book. The context in
which the question occurs is part of what makes it possible, but the evidence of
usage (the actions of an enormous interpretive community) confirm that the form of
the question is highly relevant to its interpretation and to the context in which
it is used. And even if the evidence presented here is not accepted as definitive,
it must be remembered that Fish provides no evidence at all for his claims about
the three possible meanings for the question. His assertions are based purely on
intuition.
William Golding, Stanley Fish, and the Significance of Shrinking Sticks
Finally let us consider Fish’s famous attack on stylistics, “What is Stylistics and Why are They Saying Such Terrible Things About
It?”, chapter two of
Is There a Text in This
Class?
[
Fish 1980]. I do not want to rehash this old debate, but rather to
discuss one central literary example he raises. Fish rejects M. A. K. Halliday’s
analysis of William Golding’s second novel,
The
Inheritors, and specifically the link that Halliday asserts between the
linguistic characteristics of the text and its interpretation.
The Inheritors is told from the point of view of a
Neanderthal named “Lok,” as his people are invaded and destroyed by more
modern humans, and our sentence for discussion appears in bold type in the
following passage from the novel:
The man turned sideways in the bushes and looked at Lok along his shoulder.
A stick rose upright and there was a lump of bone in the middle. Lok peered
at the stick and the lump of bone and the small eyes in the bone things over
the face. Suddenly Lok understood that the man was holding the stick out to
him but neither he nor Lok could reach across the river. He would have
laughed if it were not for the echo of the screaming in his head. The stick began to grow shorter at both ends. Then it
shot out to full length again.
The dead tree by Lok's ear acquired a voice.
“Clop!”
His ears twitched and he turned to the tree. By his face there had grown a
twig: a twig that smelt of other, and of goose, and of the bitter berries
that Lok's stomach told him he must not eat. [Golding 1955, 106]
As this brief excerpt shows, the novel’s limited point of view presents
difficulties of interpretation for the reader: Lok does not know what bows and
arrows are and cannot (yet) imagine one person attacking another, but Golding must
make us see that the man has just shot a poisoned arrow at him. Halliday’s
analysis argues that the reader’s difficulty is at least partly explained by the
peculiar Neanderthal notion of agency, in which a stick might change length by
itself, and by the novel’s limited vocabulary, in which there are no arrows or
arrowheads, no bows or the drawing of them, and no poison, but rather “a
twig,”
“a lump of bone,”
“a stick,” and “bitter berries.” Fish rejects Halliday’s claim that the
unusual features of the text force the reader to reinterpret “The stick began to
grow shorter at both ends” as the drawing of the bow:
The link between the language and any
sense we have of Neanderthal man is fashioned in response to the demands of
the reading experience; it does not exist prior to that experience, and in
the experience of another work it will not be fashioned, even if the work
were to display the same formal features. In any number of contexts, the
sentence “the stick grew shorter at both ends” would present no
difficulty for a reader; it would require no effort of reinterpretation, and
therefore it would not take on the meaning which that effort creates in
The Inheritors.
[Fish 1980, 84]
Fish may be right that a reader will not necessarily understand this sentence to
mean that a bow has been drawn without the context in which it occurs, but my
experience has been that the passage alone is sufficient context for many readers.
(It seems pointless to quibble that he has misquoted the sentence; if the text is
not the source of the meaning, that should be irrelevant in any case.) But in any
context, the sentence shapes any normal reader's interpretation in very definite
ways–simply by virtue of its grammatical and lexical characteristics and the
grammar and lexicon of English that the reader has learned. The reader must find
some way of assimilating the fact that the stick changes length by itself, and
most readers will reinterpret this sentence by adding the agency that Lok does not
understand.
I have suggested that this sentence might seem relatively normal in a description
of a magic trick or a campfire [
Hoover 1999, 23–4], but an
examination of its occurrences in large corpora suggests further ramifications
that I had not considered: “grow shorter” is essentially an oxymoron, and so
might be expected to be uncommon. The metaphor of “becoming larger is
growing” is a cognitively grounded one in which increasing in size is
modeled on growth, our preeminent natural example of increase in size, and one
that we have all intimately experienced. Inanimate objects do not generally
increase in size without an external cause, and the best examples for the metaphor
are glaciers, rivers, lakes, lava flows, avalanches, and objects like snowballs
rolling down hills, balloons, or crystals. The best examples of decrease in size
are compression, shrinking, erosion, melting, and deflation.
Without “stick” the phrase “grow shorter” seems quite ordinary, in
spite of being an oxymoron, and there are ten examples of a form of “grow”
followed by “shorter” in the BNC:
- The architecture of triticale was altered so that it would grow
shorter
- new selection pressure, and will be pushed towards growing shorter
coats again.
- Nevertheless, I worry about you as the days grow shorter
- As the days grew shorter, the Rectory colder, the pleasure they
took
- emotional and intellectual life as the autumn days grew shorter
- [estimates of] around 2,000 million years, have been growing shorter
anyway
- all of them found their attention span had grown shorter
- [nylon cords] may be showing signs of old age, knotted and growing
shorter
- The stick began to grow shorter at both ends
- The stick began to grow shorter at both ends.
It seems quite significant that two of the ten examples even of this relatively
ordinary phrase are quotations from
The Inheritors.
Only the first two of the ten use “grow” in the biological sense. In all the
others “grow” can be replaced by “become” and only the sentence from
The Inheritors describes an object changing size
in real time. In comparison, there are thirty-nine examples of a form of
“grow” followed by “longer” in the BNC. Perhaps surprisingly, only
nine of these refer to biological growth, and none of the thirty-nine describes an
object changing size in real time. (Surprises are the norm when reading a
concordance [
Sinclair 2003], [
Sinclair 2004]). Phrases
with forms of “become” instead of “grow” are even less frequent.
A Google search for forms of “grow shorter” (7/20/06) returns tens of
thousands of hits, but an examination of several hundred of them suggests that
things that grow shorter tend to fall into a few main categories:
- days and other periods of time, cycles, hospital stays
- articles of clothing, hair, body parts and plant parts (become shorter
over time, or from one generation to the next)
- temper, patience
- meetings, lectures, speeches, phone calls, letters, lists, sentences,
words
- distances
- fuses, candles, cigarettes, cigars, wicks
It is easy to see that the predominant meaning of “grow shorter” is
“become shorter”, that the process of shortening is typically one that
takes place in stages (especially for physical objects), and that many of the
things that become shorter are abstract. By far the most frequent item that grows
shorter is “days,” as the BNC list above also suggests (“grow shorter”
returns more than 100,000 hits; “days grow shorter” returns more than
55,000). When physical objects actually diminish in size, they are usually being
consumed by fire. Finally, there is a smattering of examples that are relevant to
The Inheritors: those that belong to the realms of
fantasy and magic, including transformation stories and role-playing games.
Textual evidence shows that even the relatively ordinary “grow shorter” is
significantly constrained, especially when the subject of the verb is a physical
object and the change is taking place in the present, in real time. And this
evidence supports Halliday’s claims about the oddness of Golding’s sentence and
suggests a cause for the reader’s reaction.
Returning to the full sentence makes this point more forcefully. A Google search
for “the stick began to grow shorter at both ends” (7/20/06) returns only
eight hits, all quotations from The Inheritors, and
dropping “at both ends” returns four additional slightly variant quotations.
A more recent search (7/2/07) returns twenty-one hits, but all are still from the
novel, as are the eight additional hits returned by dropping “at both ends.”
Many six-word sequences from novels will return only quotations as hits, however,
so that it seems reasonable to expand the search by focusing on the crux of the
sentence: “stick grew shorter.” This returns only four additional hits: one
is a paraphrase of Golding, two are duplicates in which a walking stick is worn
away on a long journey, and in the other the stick shortens as it burns. There is
one example of “[observed my searing] stick grow shorter”, which refers to
smoking a cigarette. There are no hits for “stick grows shorter”, but an
earlier search (12/22/05) returned one example referring to cigarette smoking. A
search for “stick grew longer” returns only one hit, in a history of hockey,
where it describes the use of successively longer sticks, but there were three
other interesting hits in my earlier search, one a dream sequence in which a sharp
stick threateningly lengthens toward the dreamer’s face and two pieces of fantasy
fiction, one of which involves the explicit use of magical dust. Fish’s claim that
Golding’s sentence would present no difficulty in “any number of contexts”
begins to seem quite doubtful, and a text-analytic corpus approach both provides
unexpected insights and gives us access to evidence about how sentences are
used–evidence that seems far more reliable than that of unaided intuition.
A much larger corpus would be useful in examining how and what Golding’s sentence
means, but the examples I have found suggest that sticks grow shorter only in
extremely limited contexts outside Golding’s novel, either in relatively prosaic
contexts where they are burnt up or wear away, or in the fantastic contexts of
dreams and magic. Golding’s sentence has precisely the effect Halliday claims for
it: it pushes us into a (necessarily fantastic) Neanderthal world in which
inanimate objects are not really inanimate, in which Lok’s feet are “clever”
and can see, in which logs might crawl off on business of their own. In which
passages like this make sense:
“The stone is a good stone,” said Lok. “It has not gone away. It
has stayed by the fire until Mal came back to it.”
He stood up and peered over the earth and stones down the slope. The
river had not gone away either or the mountains. The overhang had waited
for them. Quite suddenly he was swept up by a tide of happiness and
exultation. Everything had waited for them: Oa had waited for them. Even
now she was pushing up the spikes of the bulbs, fattening the grubs,
reeking the smells out of the earth, bulging the fat buds out of every
crevice and bough. [Golding 1955, 31–2]
Part of the power of “the stick began to grow shorter at both ends” is in the
shape of Lok’s incomprehension. For Lok, the whole world is alive, so that a stick
that changes length is perfectly comprehensible. Readers of the novel, which is
full of passages like the one above, come to see this animistic view as no mere
personification, but rather as an integral part of Lok’s world view, his mind
style. They also comprehend what he does not, until it is too late–the murderous
agency of his enemy, the bender of the bow.
It is true that an appropriate context is required to interpret Golding’s
Neanderthal world, as Fish so forcefully argues, but to focus only on the
interpretive community as a source of possible interpretations of texts is not
only to ignore the creative acts of the writers who created those texts, but also
to deny ourselves access to the most crucial element of the context in which a
reader interprets The Inheritors: the novel itself.
Any theoretical position that ignores, devalues, or rejects the text merely
encourages sloppy thinking and foolish interpretations.
Conclusion
It is time for a return to the text, specifically the electronic, computable text, to
see what scholarly digital editions, corpora, text-analysis, statistical stylistics,
and text-alteration can reveal about meanings and style. Scholarly digital editions
deepen our understanding of texts even as they problematize them, especially by
providing easy access to multiple versions of texts. Corpus analysis can reveal
hidden “semantic prosodies” and
multi-word meaning structures that have eluded thousands of years of textual study
[
Louw 1993], and can clarify and confirm the meaningfulness of a
text’s vocabulary. It can even be used to fine-tune a translation by selecting words
with appropriate frequencies and contexts [
Goldfield 2006]. Contra
Chomsky, McGann, and Fish, we can
Trust the Text
[
Sinclair 2004]. Corpora can also provide usable norms for stylistic
analysis and genre definition [
Biber 1995], and can show that authentic
texts offer a surer basis than introspection for linguistic analysis. While
recognizing the contribution of the reader, text-analysis can reveal kinds and levels
of meaning that are otherwise unrecoverable [
Stubbs 1996], and
statistical stylistics and authorship attribution can provide powerful new tools for
understanding the statistical basis of style [
Burrows 2002a], [
Burrows 2002b], [
Burrows 2002b], [
Burrows 2007], [
Hoover 2004b], [
Hoover 2004c], [
Hoover 2007]. Finally, even the easy malleability of electronic
texts can be put to more constructive uses: altering a literary text is often the
most effective way of understanding it [
Hoover 2004a], [
Hoover 2006]. There is much to be done, and many more ways of doing it
than I have described, but the stage seems finally set for a much fuller realization
of the value of electronic texts, for the end of the irrelevant text.
Works Cited
BNC World 2001
The British National Corpus, version 2 (BNC World). Distributed by
Oxford University Computing Services on behalf of the BNC
Consortium, 2001.
http://www.natcorp.ox.ac.uk
Biber 1995
Biber, D.
Dimensions of Register Variation: A Cross-linguistic
Comparison. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ.
Press, 1995.
Burrows 2002a
Burrows, J. F.
“The Englishing of Juvenal: Computational Stylistics and
Translated Texts”. Style
36 (2002): 677-99.
Burrows 2002b
Burrows, J. F.
“
‘Delta’: A Measure of Stylistic Difference and a Guide to Likely
Authorship”. Literary and Linguistic Computing
17 (2002): 267-287.
Burrows 2007
Burrows, J. F.
“All the Way Through: Testing for Authorship in Different
Frequency Strata”. Literary and Linguistic
Computing
22 (2007): 27-47.
Chomsky 1975
Chomsky, N.
Reflections on Language. New York:
Pantheon Books, 1975.
Chomsky 1986
Chomsky, N.
Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use.
New York: Praeger,
1986.
Chomsky 2000
Chomsky, N.
New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind.
Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press,
2000.
Faulkner 1978
Faulkner, W.
“A Rose for Emily”. In R. V. Cassill, The Norton Anthology of Short Fiction (3rd ed.), New
York: Norton, 1978, 431-38.
Fish 1980
Fish, S.
Is There a Text in This Class?
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1980.
Goldfield 2006
Goldfield, J.
“French-English Literary Translation Aided by Frequency
Comparisons from ARTFL and Other Corpora”. Digital
Humanities 2006. Paris: Centre de
Recherche Cultures Anglophones et Technologies de l’Information,
2006, 76-8.
Golding 1955
Golding, W.
The Inheritors. London:
Faber & Faber, 1955.
Halliday 1981
Halliday, M. A. K.
“Linguistic Function and Literary Style: An Inquiry into the
Language of William Golding's The Inheritors”. In D. C. Freeman, Essays in Modern Stylistics, London:
Methuen, 1981, 325-60.
Hoover 1999
Hoover, D. L.
Language and Style in The Inheritors. Lanham,
Md: University Press of America,
1999.
Hoover 2004a
Hoover, D. L.
“Altered Texts, Altered Worlds, Altered Styles”. Language and Literature
13(2) (2004): 99-118.
Hoover 2004b
Hoover, D. L.
“Delta Prime”? Literary and
Linguistic Computing
19 (2004): 477-495.
Hoover 2004c
Hoover, D. L.
“Testing Burrows’s Delta”. Literary
and Linguistic Computing
19 (2004): 453-475.
Hoover 2006
Hoover, D. L.
“Hot-Air Textuality: Literature after Jerome McGann”.
Text Technology, 15(1) (2006): 75-107.
Hoover 2007
Hoover, D. L.
“Corpus Stylistics, Stylometry, and the Styles of Henry
James”, Style
41(2) (2007): 160-189.
Louw 1993
Louw, B.
“Irony in the Text or Insincerity in the Writer? The Diagnostic
Potential of Semantic Prosodies”. In M. Baker, G. Francis, and E.
Tognini-Bonelli, Text and Technology.
Philadelphia: Benjamins,
1993, 157-76.
McGann 2004
McGann, J. J.
Radiant Textuality: Literature After the World Wide Web.
New York: Palgrave,
2004.
Sampson 2005
Sampson, G.
The “Language Instinct” Debate (rev. ed.).
London: Continuum, 2005.
Shillingsburg 2006
Shillingsburg, Peter L.
From Gutenberg to Google: Electronic Representations of Literary
Texts. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ.
Press, 2006.
Sinclair 2003
Sinclair, J.
Reading Concordances: An Introduction.
Harlow: Longman,
2003.
Sinclair 2004
Sinclair, J.
Trust the Text: Language, Corpus and Discourse.
London: Routledge,
2004.
Stubbs 1996
Stubbs, M.
Text and Corpus Analysis: Computer-Assisted Studies of Language
and Culture. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1996.
Trillin 1998
Trillin, C.
“The Trouble with Transcripts”. Time
151.19 (May 18, 1998): 34.